COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY IN THE CITY OF NEW YORK

PUBLICATION NUMBER FIVE

OF THE ERNEST KEMPTON ADAMS FUND FOR PHYSICAL RESEARCH

ESTABLISHED DECEMBER 17th, 1904

FOUR LECTURES ON MATHEMATICS

DELIVERED AT COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY IN 1911

BT

J. HADAMARD

HEUBER OF THE INSTITUTE, PROFESSOR IN THE COLLEGE DE FRANCE AND IN THE ficOLR POLYTECHNIQUE, LECTURER IN MATHEMATICS AND MATHEMATICAL PHTSICS IN COLUMBIA UNIVEB8ITT FOR 1911

NEW YORK

COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY PRESS

1915

ftcus*

Copyright 1915 by Columbia University Press

37/

PRESS OF

THE NEW ERA PRINTING COMPANY

LANCASTER, PA.

1915

On the seventeenth day of December, nineteen hundred and four, Edward Dean Adams, of New York, established in Columbia University "The Ernest Kempton Adams Fund for Physical Research'' as a memorial to his son, Ernest Kempton Adams, who received the degrees of Electrical Engineering in 1897 and Master of Arts in 1898, and who devoted his life to scientific research. The income of this fund is, by the terms of the deed of gift, to be devoted to the maintenance of a research fellowship and to the publication and distribution of the results of scien- tific research on the part of the fellow. A generous interpretation of the terms of the deed on the part of Mr. Adams and of the Trustees of the University has made it possible to issue these lectures as a publication of the Ernest Kempton Adams Fund.

Publications of the Ernest Kempton Adams Fund for Physical Research

Number One. Fields of Force. ByViLHELM Friman Koren Bjerkneb, Professor of Physics in the University of Stockholm. A course of lectures delivered at Columbia Univer- sity, 1905-6.

Hydrodynamic fields. Electromagnetic fields. Analogies between the two. Supplementary lecture on application of hydrodynamics to meteorology. 160 pp.

Number Two. The Theory of Electrons and its Application to the Phenomena of Light and

Radiant Heat. By H. A. Lorentz, Professor of Physics in the University of Leyden.

A course of lectures delivered at Columbia University, 1906-7. With added notes.

332 pp. Edition exhausted. Published in another edition by Teubner. Number Three. Eight Lectures on Theoretical Physics. By Max Planck, Professor of

Theoretical Physics in the University of Berlin. A course of lectures delivered at

Columbia University in 1909, translated by A. P. Wills, Professor of Mathematical

Physics in Columbia University.

Introduction: Reversibility and irreversibility. Thermodynamic equilibrium in dilute solutions.

Atomistic theory of matter. Equation of state of a monatomic gas. Radiation, electrodynamic theory.

Statistical theory. Principle of 1 east work. Principle of relativity. 130 pp.

Number Four. Graphical Methods. By C. Rcnge, Professor of Applied Mathematics in the University of Gottingen. A course of lectures delivered at Columbia University, 1909-10.

Graphical calculation. The graphical representation of functions of one or more independent variables. The graphical methods of the differential and integral ca 'cuius. 148 pp.

Number Five. Four Lectures on Mathematics. By J. Hadamard, Member of the Institute, Professor in the College de France and in the Eeole Polytechnique. A course of lectures delivered at Columbia University in 1911.

Linear partial differential equations and boundary conditions. Contemporary researches in differen- tial and integral equations. Analysis situs. Elementary solutions of partial differential equations and Green's functions. 53 pp.

Nurhber Six. Researches in Physical Optics, Part I, with especial reference to the radiation of electrons. By R. W. Wood, Adams Research Fellow, 1913, Professor of Experimental Physics in the Johns Hopkins University. 131pp. With 10 plates. Edition exhausted.

Number Seven. Neuere Probleme der theoretischen Physik. By W. Wien, Professor of Physics in the University of Wurzburg. A course of six lectures delivered at Columbia University in 1913.

Introduction: Derivation of the radiation equation. Specific heat theory of Debye. Newer radiation theory of Planck. Theory of electric conduction in metals, electron theory for metals. The Einstein fluctuations. Theory of Rontgen rays. Method of determining wave length. Photo-electric effect and emission of light by canal ray particles. 76 pp.

These publications are distributed under the Adams Fund to many libraries and to a limited number of individuals, but may also be bought at cost from the Columbia University Press.

Digitized by the Internet Archive

in 2007 with funding from

Microsoft Corporation

http://www.archive.org/details/fourlecturesonmaOOhadauoft

.••

PREFACE

The " Saturday Morning Lectures " delivered by Pro- fessor Hadamard at Columbia University in the fall of 1911, on subjects that extend into both mathematics and physics, were taken down by Dr. A. N. Goldsmith of the College of the City of New York, and after revision by the author in 1914 are now published for the benefit of a wider audience. The author has requested that his thanks be ex- pressed in this place to Dr. Goldsmith for writing out and revising the lectures, and to Professor Kasner of Columbia for reading the proofs.

in

CONTENTS

Lecture I. The Definition of Solutions of Linear Partial Differential Equations by Boundary Con- ditions.

Lecture II. Contemporary Researches in Differential Equations, Integral Equations, and In- tegro-Differential Equations.

Lecture III. Analysis Situs in Connection with Corres- pondences and Differential Equations.

Lecture IV. Elementary Solutions of Partial Differential Equations and Green's Functions.

»

LECTURE I

The Determination of Solutions of Linear Partial Dif- ferential Equations by Boundary Conditions

In this lecture we shall limit ourselves to the consideration of linear partial differential equations of the second order.

It is natural that general solutions of these equations were first sought, but such solutions have proven to be capable of successful employment only in the case of ordinary differential equations. In the case of partial differential equations employed in connection with physical problems, their use must be given up in most circumstances, for two reasons: first, it is in gen- eral impossible to get the general solution or general integral; and second, it is in general of no use even when it is obtained.

Our problem is to get a function which satisfies not only the differential equation but also other conditions as well; and for this the knowledge of the general integral may be and is very often quite insufficient. For instance, in spite of the fact that we have the general solution of Laplace's equation, this does not enable us to solve, without further and rather complicated calculations, ordinary problems depending on that equation such as that of electric distribution.

Each partial differential equation gives rise, therefore, not to one general problem, consisting in the investigation of all solu- tions altogether, but to a number of definite problems, each of them consisting in the research of one peculiar solution, defined, not by the differential equation alone, but by the system of that equation and some accessory data.

The question before us now is how these data may be chosen in order that the problem shall be "correctly set." But what do we mean by "correctly set"? Here we have to proceed by analogy.

2 FIRST LECTURE

In ordinary algebra, this term would be applied to problems in which the number of the conditions is equal to that of the unknowns. To those our present problems must be analogous. In general, correctly set problems in ordinary algebra are char- acterized by the fact of having solutions, and in a finite number. (We can even characterize them as having a unique solution if the problem is linear, which case corresponds to that of our present study.) Nevertheless, a difficulty arises on account of exceptional cases.

Let us consider a system of linear algebraic equations:

(1)

the number n of these equations being precisely equal to the number of unknowns. If the determinant formed by the co- efficients of these equations is not zero, the problem has only one solution. If the determinant is zero, the problem is in general impossible. At a first glance, this makes our aforesaid criterion ineffective, for there seems to be no difference between that case and that in which the number of equations is greater than that of the unknowns, where impossibility also generally exists. (Geometrically speaking, two straight lines in a plane do not meet if they are parallel, and in that they resemble two straight lines given arbitrarily in three-dimensional space.) The dif- ference between the two cases appears if we choose the b's (second members of the equation (1) ) properly; that is, in such manner that the system becomes again possible. If the number of equations were greater than n, the solution would (in general) again be unique; but, if those two numbers are equal, the problem when ceasing to be impossible, proves to be indeterminate.

Things occur in the same way for every problem of algebra. For instance, the three equations

/(•'•> y,z) = a

g(.r, y, z) = b

f+g = c

*

»

LINEAR PARTIAL DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS 3

between the three unknowns x, y, z, constitute an impossible system if c is not equal to a + b, but if c equals a + b, that system is in general indeterminate.

Moreover, this fact has been both extended and made precise by a most beautiful theorem due to Schoenflies.

Let

(2) /(*, y, z) = X, g(x, y, z) = Y, h(x, y, z) = Z

be the equations of a space-transformation, the functions /, g, h being continuous. Let us suppose that within a given sphere (x2 + y2 + z2 — 1, for instance), two points (x, y, z) cannot give the same single point (X, Y, Z) : in other words, that f(x, y, z) = /0'> y', z')> g(x, y, z) = g(x', y', z'): h(x, y, z) = h(x', y', z') cannot be verified simultaneously within that sphere unless x = x1 ', y — y' ', z = z' . Let S denote the surface corresponding to the surface s of the sphere; that is, the surface described by the point (A", Y, Z) when {x, y, z) describes s. If in equation (2) we consider now X, Y, Z as given and x, y, z as unknown, our hypothesis obviously means that those equations cannot admit of more than one solution within s. Now Schoenflies' theorem says that those equations will admit of a solution for any (X, Y, Z) that may be chosen within S. Of course the theorem holds for spaces of any number of dimensions. It is obvious that this theorem illustrates most clearly the aforesaid relation between the fact of the solution being unique and the fact that that solution necessarily exists.1

As said above, the theorem is in the first place remarkable for its great generality, as it implies concerning the functions /, g, h no other hypothesis but that of continuity. But its significance is in reality much more extensive and covers also the functional field. I consider that its generalizations to that field cannot

1 We must note nevertheless, that in it the unique solution is opposed not only to solutions in infinite number (as above), but also to«any more than one. For instance, the fact that x2 = X may have no solution in x, is. from the point of view of Schoenflies' theorem, in relation with the fact that for other values of X, it may have two solutions.

4 FIRST LECTURE

fail to appear in great number as a consequence of future dis- coveries. This remarkable importance will be my excuse for digressing, although the theorem in question is only indirectly related to our main subject. The general fact which it emphasizes and which we stated in the beginning, finds several applications in the questions reviewed in this lecture. It may be taken as a criterion whether a given linear problem is to be considered as analogous to the algebraic problems in which the number of equations is equal to the number of unknown. This will be the case always when the problem is possible and determinate and sometimes even when it is impossible, if it cannot cease (by further particularization of the data) to be impossible otherwise than by becoming indeterminate.

Let us return to partial differential equations. Cauchy was the first to determine one solution of a differential equa- tion from initial conditions. For an ordinary equation such as f(x, y, dy/dx, d?y/dx2) = 0, we are given the values of y and dy/dx for a particular value of x. Cauchy extended that result to partial differential equations.

Let F{u, x, y, z, du/dx, du/dy, du/dz, d2u/dx2, • • • ) = 0 be a given equation of the second order and let it be granted that we can solve it with respect to d2u/dx2. Thus we obtain (d2u/dx2) + Fi = 0 where Fi is a function of all of the above quantities, except dhi/dx2. Then Cauchy's problem arises by giving the values

OIL

(3) u = <p(y, z), ^ - \p(y, z)

of u and du/dx for x = 0. (These data must be replaced by analogous data if, instead of the plane x = 0, we introduce another surface.) Indeed, under the above hypothesis concerning the possibility of solving the equation with respect to d2u/dx2, and on the supposition that the functions F\, <f> and \p are holo- morphic, Cauchy, and after him, Sophie Kowalevska, showed that in this case there is indeed one and only one solution. This solution can be expanded by Taylor's series in the form u — u0 + xu\ + xhii + • • • where u0, Wi, • • • can be calculated.

»

LINEAR PARTIAL DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS 5

The above theorems are true for most equations arising in connection with physical problems, for example

(E) v>M=f|.

But in general these theorems may be false. This we shall realize if we consider Dirichlet's problem: to determine the solution of Laplace's equation

for points within a given volume when given its values at every point of the boundary surface S of that volume.

It is a known fact that this problem is a correctly set one: it has one, and only one, solution. Therefore, this cannot be the case with Cauchy's problem, in which both u and one of its derivatives are given at every point of S. If the first of these data is by itself (in conjunction with the differential equation) sufficient to determine the unknown function, we have no right to introduce any other supplementary condition. How is it therefore that, by the demonstration of Sophie Kowalevska, the same problem with both data proves to be possible?

Two discrepancies appear between the sense of the question in one case and in the other: (a) In the theorem of Sophie Kowalevska, u has only to exist in the immediate neighborhood of the initial surface <S. In Dirichlet's problem, it has to exist and to be well determined in the whole volume limited by S. We therefore require more in the latter case than in the former, and it might be thought that this is sufficient to resolve the apparent contradiction met with above.

In fact, however, this is not the case and we must also take account of the second discrepancy, (b) The data, in the case of the Cauchy-Kowalevska demonstration, are, as we said, sup- posed to be analytic: the functions <p, \j/ (second members of (3)) considered as functions of y, z, are taken as given by con- vergent Taylor's expansions in the neighborhood of every point

6 FIRST LECTURE

of the plane x = 0 in the region where the question is to be solved. Nothing of the kind is supposed in the study of Dirichlet's problem. Not even the existence of the first derivatives of u, corresponding to displacements on <S, is postulated, and in some researches, certain discontinuities of these values are admitted. Both these circumstances play their role in the explanation of the difference between the two results discussed above.

That (a) is one reason for that difference is evident, for of course, if a function is required to be harmonic (i. e. to admit everywhere derivatives and to verify Laplace's equation) within a sphere, its values and those of its normal derivative, may not together be chosen arbitrarily on the surface even if analytic.

To show that (a) is not sufficient for the required explanation, let us take the geometric terms of the problem in the same way as Cauchy. We therefore suppose that, u being defined by Laplace's equation, the accessory data given to determine it are the values of u, and du/dx on the plane x — 0, or, more exactly, on a certain portion A of that plane; u will also not be required, now, to exist in the whole space; its domain of existence may be limited, for instance, to a certain distance, however small, from our plane x = 0 (in the environs of 0) provided that distance be finite and not infinitesimal.

Now under these conditions, in general such a function u does not exist, if the data are not analytic and are chosen arbi- trarily. One sees then a fact which never appeared as long as ordinary differential equations were alone concerned, namely, that the results are utterly different according as the analytic character of the data is postulated or not.

3.

Of these two opposite results which is to be considered as giving us a more correct and adequate idea of the nature of things? I do not say as the true one, for of course each one is so under proper specifications.

Some mathematicians still incline to prefer the old point

LINEAR PARTIAL DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS 7

of view of Cauchy, one of their reasons being that, as known since Weierstrass, any function, analytic or not, can be replaced with any given approximation by an analytic one, (more pre- cisely by a polynomial). Therefore the fact that a function belongs to one or the other of those two categories seems to them to be immaterial. I cannot agree with this point of view. That the thing is not immaterial, seems to me to follow directly from what we have just stated. And it cannot fail to be put in evidence if we think not only of the mere existence of the solu- tion, but of its properties and the means of calculating it. If Cauchy 's problem, for equation (e), ceases to be possible, as a rule, when the functions designated by <p, \f/ are not analytic, then every expression for the solution must depend essentially on that analyticity and especially upon the radii of convergence of the developments of <p, if/. In other words, let us imagine that the functions <p, ip be replaced by other functions <p\, \pi, the differences <p\ — <p, yp\ — \f/ being very small for every system of real values of y, x within Q (and perhaps also the differences of some derivatives being small). However slight the alteration may be it rigorously follows from the afore- said theorem of Weierstrass, that the radii of convergence of the developments in power series (if existing at all) may and will be, in general, completely changed; so the calculations lead- ing to the solution will necessarily be changed also.

If that solution itself should undergo but a slight change, this would at once show us that these methods of calculation ought to be of quite an artificial nature, masking completely the quali- tative properties of the required result.1 But in fact, it is clear chat matters are not as just assumed above. The alteration Mi — u produced on the values of u by our slight modification

1 The solution by development in Taylor's series is, in general, for problems of that kind, the only one which can be given. I know but one exception, which is Schwarz's method for minimal surfaces, when a curve of the surface and the corresponding succession of tangent planes are given. This method rests on the favorable and exceptional circumstance that complex variables can be employed for the study of real points of such a surface.

8 FIRST LECTURE

of <p, \p will be generally important and often complete, as is evident1 by the fact that u will cease completely to exist when <p, $ become non-analytical. This proves, first of all, that the application of Weierstrass' theorem in that case is illegitimate, since it gives an approximation for the data but nothing of the kind for the unknown.

Then we see also that such a problem and calculation, the results of which are utterly changed by an infinitesimal error in starting, can have no meaning in their applications.

This leads to my second and chief reason for considering only the results which correspond to non-analytic data, namely, the remarkable accordance between them and the results to which physical applications bring us.

This accordance is the more interesting from the fact of its results being unexpected. Our former point of view — i. e. that of the Cauchy-Kowalevska theorem — evidently constitutes a complete analogy to the case of ordinary differential equations. But from our latter point of view — which is also the point of view in problems set by physical applications — every analogy seems to be upset. The results often seem almost inco- herent, they will give opposite conclusions in apparently similar questions.

A first instance of this was given above. We know that Cauchy's problem is now impossible for Laplace's equation

d2u d2u d2u fa2+df+d?

but, on the contrary, in the equation of spherical waves

W dx2~*~ dy2_t~ dz2 dt2 '

1 If Mi — u should be uniformly very small at the same time as <pi — <p, \fn — 41, it follows from the well-known convergence theorem of Cauchy that, letting the analytic functions (pi, <l>\, converge towards certain (non-analytic) limiting functions <p, ip, the corresponding solution «i ought to converge uniformly towards a certain limit u, which would be solution of the problem with the data <e, $.

(«) A*u== ^72 + ^72+^2 = 0;

LINEAR PARTIAL DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS 9

or of the cylindrical waves

<E>) — + —

^ ; dx* + dp?

we may assign arbitrarily the values (whether analytical or not) of u and hujU for t = 0, and Cauchy's problem set in that way has a solution (which is unique). In this latter case it is like a problem in algebra in which the number of equations is equal to the number of unknowns; in the former, like a problem in which the number of equations is superior1 to the number of unknowns.

It never could have been imagined a priori that such a difference could depend on the mere changing of sign of a coefficient in the equation. But it is entirely conformable to the physical meaning of the equations. Equation (E'), for instance governs the small motions of a homogeneous and isotropic medium, like a homogeneous gas; and the corresponding Cauchy's problem, enunciated above, represents the definition of the motion by giving the state of positions and speeds at the origin of times. On the contrary, equation (e), which also governs many physical phenomena, never leads to problems of that kind but exclusively to problems of the Dirichlet type. The analytical criterion by which those two kinds of partial differential equations are to be distinguished, is known: it is given by what are called the characteristics of an equation. The characteristics of an equa tion jrrespond analytically with what the physicist calls the waves compatible with this equation, and are calculated in the following way. Let a wave be represented by the equation P(x, y, z, t)

1 We could be tempted to apply in that case the remark made in the be- ginning (p. 4) concerning such impossible problems, which, notwithstanding that circumstance, must be considered as resembling "correctly set" ones. This, however, is not really applicable; for we have seen that the category alluded to is recognized by the fact that the problem may, under more special circumstances, become indeterminate. Now, this can never be the case in the present question: it follows from a theorem of Holmgren ("Archiv fiir Mathematik") that the solution of Cauchy's problem, if existent, is in every possible case unique.

10 FIRST LECTURE

= 0. In the given equation, for instance, if A2u — l/a?-d2u/d1? = 0 and A2u be replaced by (dP/dx)2 + (dP/dy)2 + (dP/dz)2 and - (l/a2)(d2u/dP) by - (l/a2)(dP/dt)2 the condition thus obtained

(which is a partial differential equation of the first order). It must be verified by the function P. When this holds, P(x, y, z, t) = 0 is said to be a characteristic of the given equation.

For equation (E), such characteristics exist (that is, are real); this case is called the hyperbolic one.

Laplace's equation, A2u = 0, on making the above substitu- tion, leads to the equation

which has no real solution. Therefore, in this case there are no waves and we have the so-called elliptic case.1 Cauchy's problem can be set for a hyperbolic equation, but not for an elliptic one. Does this mean that for a hyperbolic equation Cauchy's problem will always arise? No, the matter is not quite so simple. For instance, in equation (E) or (E')t we could not choose arbi- trarily u and du/dy for x = 0; this would lead us again to an impossible problem (in the non-analytic case, of course).

The physical explanation of this lies in the fact that there are, besides the partial differential equation, two kinds of conditions determining the course of a phenomenon, viz., the initial and the boundary conditions. The former are of the type of Cauchy and they alone intervene in Cauchy's problem quoted above for the equation of sound.

But the boundary conditions are always of the type of Dirich- let. They are the only ones which can occur in an elliptic equation, but even in a hyperbolic one they generally present

1 An intermediate case exists A*u — k(du/dt) = 0. This is semi-definite and is termed the parabolic one (example: the equation of heat).

LINEAR PARTIAL DIFFERENTIAL EQUATIONS 11

themselves together with initial ones. This gives place to so- called mixed problems where the two kinds of data (belonging respectively to the Cauchy and to the Dirichlet type) intervene simultaneously for the determination of the unknown.

In equation (E), t = 0 represents the origin of time and can give place to initial conditions, having the form, of Cauchy. But no such conditions can correspond to x = 0, which represents a geometric boundary.

More or less complicated cases can arise for various disposi- tions of the configurations, giving place to other paradoxical and apparently contradictory results, which can however all be explained in the same way. Moreover, there are other types of linear partial differential equations,1 which do not govern any physical phenomena. The determination of solutions has been studied2 in the analytic case but no sort of determination of that kind for non-analytic data has been discovered hitherto.

We see that from this non-analytic point of view the accord- ance between mathematical results and the suggestions of physics holds perfectly. This accordance must not surprise us, for, as we saw above, it corresponds to the fact that a problem which is possible only with analytic data can have no physical meaning. But it remains worth all our attention. No other example better illustrates Poincare's views3 on the help which physics brings to analysis as expressed by him in such statements as the following: "It is physics which gives us many important problems, which we would not have thought of without it," and " It is by the aid of physics that we can foresee the solutions." 1 The so-called non-normal hyperbolic equations, such as

*» + ...** _** A2!L = 0(m>l,n>l)

dx?^ dxj dyi> dyj

* By Hamel (Inaugural Dissertation, Gottingen) and Coulon (thesis, Paris)

* Lectures delivered at the first International Mathematical Congress, Zurich, 1897; reproduced in "La Valeur de la Sciences."

LECTURE II

Contemporary Researches in Differential Equations,

Integral Equations, and Integro-Differential

Equations

1. Partial Differential Equations and, Integral Equations

I reminded you at the end of the last lecture what indispensable help the physicist renders to the mathematician in furnishing him with problems. But that help is not always free from inconveniences, and the task of the mathematician is often a thankless one. Two cases generally occur: it may happen that the physical problem is easily soluble by a mere "rule of three" method, but if not, it is so extremely difficult that the mathe- matician despairs of solving it at all ; and he will strive after that solution for two centuries and, when he obtains it, our interest in the particular physical problem may have been lost. Such seems to be the case with some problems concerning partial differential equations. Just after the discovery of infinitesimal calculus, physicists began by needing only very simple methods of integration, the problems in general reducing to elementary differential equations. But when higher partial differential equations were introduced, the corresponding problems almost immediately proved to be far above the level of those which contemporary mathematics could treat.

Indeed, those problems (such as Dirichlet's) exercised the sagacity of geometricians and were the object of a great deal of important and well-known work through the whole of the nineteenth century. The very variety of ingenious methods applied showed that the question did not cease to preserve its rather mysterious character. Only in the last years of the century were we able to treat it with some clearness and under-

12

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 13

stand its true Dature. This clearness seemed to come too late, for at that time, physics began its present evolution in which it seems to disregard partial differential equations and to come back to ordinary differential equations, but of course in prob- lems profoundly different from the simple cases which were familiar to Bernoulli! or Euler.

Happily, for it would have been a humiliating thing to work so uselessly, this disregard was only in appearance, and the ancient problems have not lost their importance by the fact that other ones have been superposed on and not substituted for them. In fact, the solution now obtained for Dirichlet's problem has proved useful in several recent researches of physics.

Let us therefore inquire by what device this new view of Dirichlet's problem and similar problems was obtained. Its peculiar and most remarkable feature consists in the fact that the partial differential equation is put aside and replaced by a new sort of equation, namely, the integral equation. This new method makes the matter as clear as it was formerly obscure.

In many circumstances in modern analysis, contrary to the usual point of view, the operation of integration proves a much simpler one than the operation of derivation. An example of this is given by integral equations where the unknown function is written under such signs of integration and not of differentia- tion. The type of equation which is thus obtained is much easier to treat than the partial differential equation.

The type of integral equations corresponding to the plane Dirichlet problem is

(1) *(*) — Xjf <S>{y)K{x, y)dy = /(*)

where <£ is the unknown function of x in the interval {A, B), f and K are known functions, and X is a known parameter. The equations of the elliptic type in many-dimensional space give similar integral equations, containing however multiple integrals and several independent variables. Before the introduction of

14 SECOND LECTURE

equations of the above type, each step in the study of elliptic partial differential equations seemed to bring with it new diffi- culties; not only did the various methods imagined for Dirichlet's problem not cast more than a partial light on the question, but the principles of most of them were peculiar to that special problem: they seemed to disappear if Laplace's equation was replaced by any other equation of the same type, or even (except for Neumann's method, which, as we shall soon see, is directly related to integral equations) if for the same Laplace's equa- tion Dirichlet's problem was replaced by any analogous one such as presented by hydrodynamics or theory of heat. Each of them, besides, was rather a proof of existence than a method of calculation.

Then they seemed again quite insufficient for another series of questions which mathematical physics had to solve, viz., the study of harmonics. The existence of those harmonics (such as the different kinds of resonance of a room filled with air) was physically evident, but for the mathematician it offers an im- mense difficulty. Schwarz, Picard and Poincare gave a first solution which was rather complicated as each harmonic requires for its definition a new infinite process of calculation after the preceding one has been determined. Nevertheless it has demon- strated rigorously the chief properties of the quantities in ques- tion (namely, certain special values of the parameter in equation (1)), i. e. that they exist and form a discrete infinity, only a finite number of them lying within any finite interval.

But at the same time a discovery even more important, in a certain sense, was made by Poincare, namely the near relation between that question of harmonics and the method which had been indicated by Neumann for Dirichlet's problem. This discove.y of Poincare paved the way for Fredholm's work. The latter treats every one of the aforesaid questions, and any which can be assimilated to them, by one and the same method, which consists in tire reduction to an equation such as (1). This gives all the required results at once and for all the possible types of such problems.

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 15

In all this, the mathematician seems to play again the unfortunate role we alluded to in the beginning; for those results are nothing but the mathematical demonstration of facts each of which was familiar to every physicist long before the beginning of all those researches. But of course their interest is not in fact limited in demonstration; they can and do serve as starting points for the discovery of new facts. They are useful as giving the proper method of calculation. Previously, in the calculation of the resonance of a room filled with air, the shape of the resonator had to be quite simple, which require- ment is not a necessary one for the case where integral equations are employed. We need only make the elementary calculation of the function K and apply to the function so calculated the general method of resolution of integral equations.

There are two chief methods for the solution of the equa- tions. It is not always easy to get numerical results.

Liouville and Neumann (in solving Dirichlet's problem) really worked out a method of solving integral equations. A second method is due to Fredholm. The first method leads to series which may converge slowly but they are easy to calculate. The method of Fredholm gives a quotient of two series (entire functions of X) the terms of which have to be calculated inde- pendently, while in the first method each is obtained from the one immediately preceding it. While we must add that Erhard Schmidt has shown how the first method can be made to supply a more rapidly convergent series, Fredholm's method is of greater value to physics because of the theoretical point of view. It gives easily (what was impossible before its appearance) not only the existence of harmonics, but their properties. For instance, older methods could not have succeeded, at least not without great difficulties and a large amount of calculation, in obtaining the order of magnitude of the successive upper har- monics (i. e. the corresponding great values of A). They would probably have been quite unable to predict the order of magni- tude, as is done in the recent works of Hermann Weyl, so as to

16 SECOND LECTURE

show its relation the volume of the room to which they correspond. But it has even proved of great importance for physics to know mathematically, and not only empirically, that the harmonics corresponding to equations of the form (1) are a discrete infinity. For in the case of the spectral frequencies we get series which tend to accumulate towards definite positions. Since Fredholm's theory we can assert that such series are not compatible with the form of integral equation given at the beginning of this lecture.

Fredholm himself investigated new forms (as also did Walther Ritz). The introduction of the integral equation has made even the above problem accessible. The older method would not have been able to decide whether the distribution in question was pos- sible or not. The hypothesis proposed by Fredholm leads to an integral equation such as

*<*> ~ kZTtf£<Kv)K(*>y)dy -/(*)

(2)

Here the frequencies will accumulate in the neighborhood of

I must immediately add that, as Ritz showed, Fredholm's type is not sufficient to give a correct explanation of the phenomena. But this does not change the essential fact that by the aid of the new method we are immediately able to decide what the asymp- totic distribution of harmonics can or cannot be, so that com- parison with observation becomes possible; and this we owe entirely to Fredholm's method.

2. Coming Back to Ordinary Differential Equations

As we said in the beginning, the subject of partial differential equations which was the main and almost the only occupation of mathematical physics, ceases nowadays to be so. As a con- sequence of the general admission of the discrete structure of matter, physical problems tend now to lead to ordinary differ- ential equations. These differential equations are to be studied

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 17

under the most difficult circumstances because we must follow the form of the solutions for very long periods of time, that is, of the independent variable t. One can say that such a study did not exist before Poincare, and even his researches on the subject, I mean especially his four chief memoirs in the " Journal de Mathematiques," 1887 {On the shape of Curves Defined by Differential Equations), lead us, like Socrates, to begin to feel that we know nothing.

We cannot, in this place, lay stress on the extraordinary com- plications and paradoxes which he discovered. We shall mention only one of them, because it helps to correct an error frequently committed in hydrodynamical and electrical problems, concern- ing the lines of force and the lines of flow. These lines are all defined by ordinary differential equations. The general form is dx/X = dy/Y = dz/Z. In a very general category of cases the vector XYZ has the property that

div {XYZ)^{~

6X dY dZ\

dx + dy+ dz)

Now, whenever such conditions existed, physicists used to say that the tubes of force — or tubes of flow, or tubes of vortices — were closed (if they did not go to infinity or come to the boundaries of the domain of existence of the vector X, Y, Z).

They were, I think, led to say so by the examples given by some simple peculiar cases in which the differential equations could be integrated, for one could not suspect before Poin- care's work that such cases are exceptional, generally giving a quite inadequate and deformed view of things. In fact, the assertion in question is an utterly false one.1 If you allow me such a crude comparison, it is not true that the tube of force must get back home and put its key in the lock. Rather does it put its key above and below and on either side, and never succeeds in getting it in exactly. It will, it is true, nearly get

1 A demonstration is frequently given to justify it, the error of which consists in an incomplete enumeration of possible cases.

18

SECOND LECTIKE

back an infinite number of times. The only consequence which can be correctly drawn from the equation div(ATZ) = 0 is that the area of the cross section of the tube cannot have changed. But its shape may, and generally will, have done so. If it were, let us say, circular in starting, it will have become elliptic when coming back and its ellipticity will increase at each return. Finally it will become a long flat strip and only a part of it will come back to the neighborhood of its original position. In Fig. 1, the successive appearances of the same tube of force are shown.

A

Via. 1

The tube of force may have been originally circular, but on its first recurrence or return, it may have become elliptic in cross section and thus it has only partly returned to its original position. Still more is this the case in the second recurrence of the tube of force, which may be assumed by this time to have become very flat in cross section.

As Mr. Birkhoff kindly pointed out to me, it is interesting to remark that in most cases, the deformed and flattened tube will even pass simultaneously indefinitely near to any point of the considered medium.

A rather curious fact must nevertheless be stated. Although the principle that the tube is closed is completely false, the

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 19

conclusions drawn from it by physicists are most often true. Why is this so? Perhaps the explanation lies in the fact that under that same hypothesis, div (X, Y, Z) = 0, a line defined by our differential equations generally returns indefinitely near and an infinite number of times to its starting point. (This is called " Stabilite a la Poisson.") Poincare has shown that though not every line in question necessarily does this, the fact occurs for an infinitely greater number of cases than those in which it does not occur.

3. Application to Molecular Physics

We see by this single example how complicated and unexpected the shapes of curves defined by differential equations may be, and how far we are from understanding them when considered for great values of the independent variable.

But could we be satisfied with our work if we succeeded in doing so? This even is doubtful. I cannot help thinking of a bequest left to the French Academy of Science for a prize to the first person who should be able to communicate with a planet other than Mars! The case of molecular physics reminds me of that rather difficult requirement. The discussion of the molar effects (i. e. the effects on quantities of matter accessible to observation) of molecular movements is a mathematical problem, which, logically speaking, would presuppose a rather advanced knowledge of curves defined by differential equations, and take this as a starting point, in order to discuss the questions of probability connected with such curves.

That probability plays its role in the movements of almost any dynamical system, follows from the statements we just quoted. If the initial positions and the initial speeds of the moving points are exactly given, so will be the final positions and speeds after any (however long) given period of time. But if this period is long, and if we make a very small error in the initial conditions, the small error will have a much magnified effect and even cause a total change in the results at the end of the long period of time, and this is precisely Poincare's conception of hazard.

20 SECOND LECTURE

It is like a roulette game at Monte Carlo where we do not know all the conditions of launching the ball which induces the hazard. And so we know nothing more about the conditions than the gamblers. In other words, molecules are finally mixed just as cards after much shuffling. It is this fundamental hazard which plays the main part in Gibbs's method. A sort of mixing func- tion ought to be introduced. Let us start on one of the lines of force. If we know exactly the point of departure A we should know accurately the point of arrival. If A is but approximately known, that point of arrival may occupy all sorts of positions; and indeed, in many differential problems, it may coincide (approximately) with any point B within the domain where the differential system is considered (though this is not exactly so for dynamical problems on account of the energy integral or other uniform integrals which the equations may admit).

Therefore, the starting point being approximately A, there will be a certain probability that the point of arrival will be in a certain neighborhood of another given point B; and that prob- ability will be a certain function of the positions of the two points A, B.

Now, logically speaking, in order to solve the question set for us by kinetic theories, we ought to take such a "mixing function," assuming it to be known, as a base for further and perhaps complicated reasoning. In fact, the main present theories in statistical mechanics rest on certain assumptions concerning that function, which are very plausible. But, rigor- ously speaking, we are not able to consider them as theorems.

Happily, things are greatly simplified by the fact that in such mixings the aforesaid function, characteristic of the law of mixing, only intervenes by some of its properties and may be changed to a large extent without changing the final result. This is what Poincare showed for the ordinary shuffling of cards in his "Calcul des Probabilities " (second edition). In one shuffling the peculiar habits of the player certainly intervene and so do they more or less after only a few shufflings. But

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 21

after many shufflings the results become totally independent of those habits. Poincare also shows (though with some excep- tions which do not however seem to play a great practical role), that such is likewise the case in the kind of mixing introduced by molecular theories.

Some known facts in the history of these theories give a striking instance of this. Such is the work of Boltzmann and Gibbs in the treatment of the kinetic theory of gases and statistical mechanics. They both obtained the result that if we consider the probability of the average number of mole- cules in 6-dimensionaI space and call it P, and integrate log P over the whole mass, the conclusion drawn will be that the integral obtained is constantly increasing. Critics, and among them my colleague and friend Brillouin, say: "We have not to congratidate ourselves on the result, because the two speak of quite different things and yet they agree. Gibbs does not mention the collision of molecules, while Boltzmann's analysis is founded on the collisions of molecules. The primitive order of the molecules is disturbed by such collisions and a mixing is produced. Gibbs gets a similar mixing by the mere considera- tion of differential equations existing over long periods of time." In both cases, if we consider systems which are "molecularly organized," after a certain time the molecules will be so much less organized and more mixed up.

We are surprised to find this coincidence of the results of Gibbs and of Boltzmann in such circumstances. We shall, how- ever, cease to consider it as fortuitous and perceive its true signification by precisely what we just remarked on the shuffling of cards, which makes us understand that such final results may and do depend on properties which are, in general, common to utterly various laws of mixing.

But the difficulties met with in partial or ordinary differential equations are not the only ones which we had to consider at the present time. The mathematicians have contrived to introduce a new sort of equation, more difficult than the previous ones, the integro-differential equation.

22 SECOND LECTURE

4. Integro-diffcrential Equations

We are now forced to consider this new form. Here the unknown function simultaneously appears in integrals and in differentials. We have at least two completely different cases of such equations to consider. Their difference corresponds to the two sorts of variables which intervene in all physical problems, the space variables x, y, z, and the time variable t. (There may be more than three variables in the first group.)

Type 1: Differentiation with respect to x, y, z; integration relative to t. Type 2: Differentiation with respect to t; integra- tion relative to x, y, z. And even though this type dates only from 1907, we have already found cases of both kinds.

Volterra was led to consider the first one in connection with "The Mechanics of Heredity." This is the case where the properties of the system depend on all the previous facts of its existence (such as magnetic hysteresis, strains of glass, and permanent deformations in general).

Volterra considers elastic hysteresis. Let T be any component of strains; E the component of deformation. (There are six 7"s and six E's.) Then formerly we considered Thk= 2ahkEkk. There are 6 equations of this type. There are 21, 36, 6 or 2 a's depend- ing on the theories. If we consider heredity, we must introduce new terms. Suppose that at the time 0 there were mo strains ; then

Thk = 2aEhk + I (2aE)tdr where t is the variable time. This

Jo is an equation in which we have derivatives with respect io x, y, z, and an integral with respect to the time; and the same character subsists if, from those values of the T's, we deduce the equations of movement. Water waves furnish us with an instance of the opposite type. One knows that waves on the surface of water are the most common example of an undulatory phenomenon and that, for this reason, they are most frequently used to give to the beginner a first idea of what such phenomena are.

But it is a general, though astonishing fact, that the most

.'•

CONTEMPORARY RESEARCHES IN EQUATIONS 23

simple of daily phenomena are the most difficult to understand. While the theory of aerial or even elastic waves is rather simple, at least as long as viscosity is left aside,1 and now classically reduced to analytical principles (related to notion of characteris- tics as we saw in the preceding lecture), the properties of surface waves in liquids are much more hidden. The few results clas- sically known on that subject are even of a contradictory nature. One of them is the differential equation given by Lagrange in the case of small (and constant) depth, which has served as a model for the dynamical theory of tides, the equation obtained as governing the phenomenon being in both cases a partial differential equation of the second order. But, for the same phenomenon on a liquid of indefinite depth, Cauchy gets a partial equation of the fourth order. The truth is that the problem does not lead to a differential equation at all, but to an integro-differential equation. Fof an originally plane surface with small displacements, where z is the vertical displacement at (x, y), then

^ = f f Z^(P, Q)dSQ

Thus, for any determinate point P of the surface defined by its coordinates, (z, y), the vertical acceleration depends on the values of z in every other point Q(x', y'). Here SQ is dx'dy' and <f> is a known function of (x, y, x', y'). The above equation is of the second form of integro-differential equations.

Volterra succeeded in the case of isotropic bodies in reducing the problem to the solution of a partial differential equation and an ordinary integral equation. But things are not so simple for crystalline media.2

1 In a viscous gas, waves cannot exist, strictly speaking. They are replaced by quasi-waves which were first considered by Duhem, and more profoundly studied in an important memoir presented by Roy to the French Academy of Sciences.

'Since these lectures were delivered, Professor Volterra has given a com- prehensive view of his methods and solutions in a course of lectures at the University of Paris. See the issue of those lectures by J Peres (Paris, Gauthier Villars).

24 SECOND LECTURE

The two types of integro-differential equations, which we just enumerated, are completely different in their treatment. Volterra's type resembles the partial differential equations (of the elliptic or sometimes parabolic genus in the examples hitherto given). The equation must be completed by accessory condi- tions which are nothing else than boundary conditions (cf. Lecture I). The methods given by Volterra run exactly parallel to those which are applied for Dirichlet's problem (such as the formation of Green's functions).

In the second type described above, the accessory condi- tions are initial ones; and are to be treated in the manner, not of partial, but of ordinary differential equations — such methods as Picard's successive approximations being of great use in that case.

LECTURE III •

Analysis Situs in Connection with Correspondences and Differential Equations

1.

We are going to speak of the role of analysis situs in our modern mathematics. This theory is also called the geometry of situation. It is the study of connections between different parts of geometrical configurations which are not altered by any con- tinuous deformation. We suppose that we can let a system undergo any deformation whatever, however arbitrary it may be, only that it preserves continuity. For instance, a sphere and a cube are considered as one and the same thing from the point of view of the geometry of situation, because one can be trans- formed into the other without separating parts, or uniting paits which formerly were separated. The circle and the rectangle are identical from the same point of view. But the lateral surface of a cylinder and the surface of a rectangle are not identical, because, for the transformation of one into the other, we must make a cut along a generatrix. Also one is limited by two lines (the base circles) while the other is limited by one. The total surface of a cylinder is entirely closed; it is identical with the surface of a sphere. There is no difficulty in the transformation.

If we consider the "anchor ring," the case is different. This is a closed surface but it has a hole which is not found in the surface of the sphere, and the surface of the sphere can- not be transformed continuously in it. It would have to be transformed by several cuts, the first of them (Fig. 2) giving a broken ring, which for us is identical with the lateral surface of a cylinder. This may be cut into a rectangle and then trans-

25

26

THIRD LECTURE

formed into a sphere. But the transformation of an anchor ring into a sphere cannot be done without cutting and piecing. The principles of analysis situs, for surfaces in ordinary space,

Fig. 2.

are well known and I do not intend to go over them at this mo- ment. We shall take them for granted. According to them,

Fia. 3.

a surface of two dimensions is defined from our present point of view by the number of boundaries and another number, namely

\

ANALYSIS SITUS

27

the genus. The genus is zero for the sphere and one for the anchor ring. For a pot with two "ears" (Fig. 3) we have the genus two.

Analysis situs started with trifling problems, such as that treated by Euler of the bridges of Konigsberg over the Pregel river. There are seven bridges; the problem is to go over all of them without passing twice over any one (Fig. 4). The great

Fia. 4.

Euler did not disdain to occupy himself with this and many other apparently childish problems. But what interests us in this one especially is that it involves the geometry of situation, in the sense in which we have used the term. For even if the islands in the river had other shapes and the bridges had the queerest forms, the reasoning would be exactly the same, pro- vided the numbers of islands and bridges should not change, and each bridge should join the same islands in both cases.

We have here an example of an important theory which develops from a childish exercise. Some would think that it was a disadvantage to mathematics that we should occupy ourselves with such problems. The fact is, as we see, that they may, though exceptionally, lead to valuable results.

That this notion of analysis situs was really an important one, appears first from the researches of Itiemann. You know that Riemann was the fellow founder with Cauchy of the modern theory of analytic functions. These two schools applied their

28

THIRD LECTURE

theories to the study of algebraic functions. Cauchy's methods, in the hands of their author and of Puiseux, were capable of casting light on some important parts of the problem, "but did not however completely elucidate it, and (in particular) Riemann alone could discover the fundamental notion of the genus of an algebraic curve.

What were the elements of Riemann's success and superiority over Cauchy? A remark must first be made which perhaps, strictly speaking, would not be within our subject, but which is nevertheless, as we shall see, most closely and necessarily connected with it.

Let us consider the real domain. Suppose that we have to study the algebraic function y defined by x2 + y2 = 1 (or any quadratic equation defining y as a function of x corresponding to an ellipse). This function is real only for values of x which are

Fig. 5.

comprised between — 1 and -f- 1 (in the second case, for values between x0 and Xi). Riemann considered the function in the seg- ment comprised between these values. He remarked that this is an incomplete view of the equation, for y is not well defined,

ANALYSIS SITUS 29

because it has two different values. But if we change our straight line into two slightly different straight lines, then we may admit that tHfe superior segment corresponds to the + value of y, and the inferior one to the — value, the two segments being supposed to join each other at their common ends. To each point of the drawing, after that modification, one and only one system of values of x and y verifying the given equation will correspond. Besides, in that case, we obtain a figure which from the point of view of analysis situs, is identical with the ellipse represented by the given equation itself.

But Riemann applied that same method in the complex domain, and was led to the celebrated kind of representing sur- faces which bear his name.

This principle is a very general one. It must be applied, in any case, before using the geometry of situation. We must inquire whether the domain used is adequate to represent the states of variation to be studied. I shall give an instance which I think is due to Sophus Lie. It is concerned with the singular solution of differential equations of the first order. Given the differential equation

f(x, y, y') = 0 (1)

the question, as well known, is whether some solution exists which is not represented in the general integral. In that case such a solution must verify not only the original equation, but also

I"0 <2>

Darboux showed that this was not sufficient, and that, in general, the system of equations (1) and (2) does not represent an actual solution, but that the curve which it defines is the locus of the cusps of the solutions of equation (1) (Fig. 5). We now shall see that this result, the analytical proof of which requires some complicated calculations, appears of itself by the above geo- metric considerations.

Equation (1) defines y' as a function of x and y, but this func-

30

THIRD LECTURE

tion has several determinations or branches. This state of things is not satisfactory from our point of view above. In order to avoid this, let us consider the surface f(x, y, z) = 0 in space. For each point of that surface, we have

dyjdx = z (3)

Fia. 6.

So that the problem becomes to trace on the suiface, those curves which have dyjdx equal to z. Geometrically speaking, such curves must, in each point, be tangent to a certain direction, viz. the intersection of the tangent plane to the surface with a certain vertical plane (represented by (3)). The system (1) and (2)

?•

ANALYSIS SITUS 31

represents the "horizontal boundary" of the surface. At each point m on it, the tangent plane is vertical (Fig. 6). What happens there? We see that in m, the two planes which define the tangent to our curve are vertical (the plane corresponding to (3) being so in any case). Therefore, this tangent itself is also vertical. This gives immediately the desired result; for it is well known that by projecting a space curve on a plane perpen- dicular to one of its tangents, we obtain a projection curve which has a cusp. The only exception would be when our two planes would coincide and this indeed gives the supplementary con- dition for the existence of a singular solution.

A difficult question in differential equations is thus recon- ducted to an elementary result of analytical geometry; and this is obtained by the mere fact of depicting correctly (in the sense of Riemann) y' as a function of x and y. Only when this ade- quate representation of the domain of variation is obtained, analysis situs is to be applied.

Before seeing it in operation, let us notice that Cauchyhad an opportunity of discovering its importance. This is a curious historical fact in his work; for it was one of his few errors. It was done in his youthful period, when dealing with the theorem of Euler on polyhedrons. This theorem connects the number of faces, summits and edges. It expresses that F -f- V = E -f- 2, where F is the number of faces, V is the number of vertices, and E the number of edges. Cauchy's demonstration was false, and so is even the theorem itself. This theorem holds effectively (and this is the reason why Euler and Cauchy believed it to be true) for a very large category of polyhedra, among which every convex one occurs. But others had been overlooked, such as those which have the general shape of an anchor ring, and these do not verify the above relation. If Cauchy had perceived that error; if he had noticed that exception to Euler's theorem, it may be presumed with some probability that he would not have left to Riemann the glory of founding a complete theory of algebraic functions.

32 THIRD LECTURE

Let me remind you of the difference between the method of Cauchy (and of Puiseux) and that of Riemann. If we consider the algebraic function defined by F(x, y) = 0, then y, in general, in the environs of x0 and yo, is a regular analytic function of x and is given by a* Taylor's series within a certain circle around x0. Inside this circle, the principles of Cauchy and Weierstrass permit us to study the function. At critical points Xi, where y is not a holomorphic function of x, Puiseux studied this. He took X = (x — ari)1/p, p being properly chosen. Then y can be developed in powers of X instead of in terms of x — X\. Everything seems at first to be settled then. But really we still ignore some fundamental properties. The reason of this is that we do not get the direct idea of the total domain, but only an indirect idea of it by a series of smaller regions.

It is true that these smaller regions are such that, taken alto- gether, they cover the totality of the domain in question, and for that reason, they finally may enable us to master it com- pletely. But the error was to believe that this could be without a special study of the manner in which those partial regions are united.

I should compare this (though the comparison is very in- complete) to the map of a large country, which is given by a series of partial leaves. We must take account, not only of each separate leaf, but of the "assembling table" showing their general disposition, so as to pass from the detail to the whole. The capital and unexpected fact, the discovery of which belongs to Riemann, is that such "assembling tables" are not at all like each other; that there are several quite different kinds of them : therefore, the synthesis of the details of the solution cannot be well understood without noticing these differences.

2.

It is now evident that the importance of these considerations is not limited to algebraic functions. They are connected with every synthesis of the above mentioned kind, that is to say,

fc

ANALYSIS SITUS 33

theoretically speaking, with every employment of integral calculus.

They constitute a sort of revenge of geometry on analysis. Since Descartes, we have been accustomed to replace each geo- metric relation by a corresponding relation between numbers, and this has created a sort of predominance of analysis. Many mathematicians fancy they escape that predominance and consider themselves as pure geometers in opposition to analysis; but most of them do so in a sense I cannot approve: they simply restrict themselves to treating exclusively by geometry questions which other geometers would treat, in general quite easily, by analytical means; they are of course, very frequently forced to choose their questions not according to their true scientific interest, but on account of the possibility of such a treatment without intervention of analysis. I am even obliged to add that some of them have dealt with problems totally lacking any interest whatever, this total lack of interest being the sole reason why such problems have been left aside by analysts. Of course, I not only admit geometrical treatment, but use it every time I find it possible, for, if applicable at all, it gives us, in general, a much better view of the subject than an analytical one. But very important problems may be inaccessible to it. We must use all means at our disposal and choose, not this or that one a priori, but the one best adapted to our question.

But here geometry has over analysis a more certain ad- vantage. I consider that analysis could not, or could only with great difficulty, and probably after a long series of sterile efforts, have replaced the geometrical views we have just alluded to for resolving the corresponding part of the problem. I mean that passage from the solution in small regions to the solution over the whole domain.1

1 Logically speaking, even the results of analysis situs can be rigorously stated in numerical language; but such statements have been made only after the results have been found, and some parts of this analytic treatment are of extreme difficulty (such as Jordan's theorem).

34 THIRD LECTURE

Let us, for instance, admit that that domain is a two-dimen- sional one. Then according to analytical methods, we ought to individualize any point of it by giving the values of two param- eters, x and y. But the representation of a geometrical problem by means of functions of x and y often makes us lose some element of the problem: functions in a domain in two dimensions may be something else than the functions of x and y. The simultaneous variation of x and y represents a plane. Now a plane has not the same general shape as a sphere or anchor ring, and those differences are lost in Descartes's method. We can have, for instance, as many examples of this difference in rational dynamics as we please. One knows that when a dynamical problem has two degrees of freedom the corre- sponding differential equations, i. e. the equations of Lagrange, are defined, the parameters which define the position of the system being designated by x and y, if one gives the expres- sion 2T = E(x, y)x'2 4- 2F(x, y)x'y' + G(x, y)y'2 for the vis viva and the expression U = <p(x, y) for the force function. There- fore, if two problems of dynamics correspond to the same ex- pression of T and the same expression of U, their studies ought to be exactly identical and reducible to each other. That mat- ters may really be quite different is to be immediately seen by the following example:

(1) Consider the material particle acted on by no forces. The trajectories will be straight lines. (2) Let us have a vertical standard. The arms AA' and BB' are solidly attached and A and B are fixed (Fig. 7). The only motion of the system is a rotation about AB. A'B' is a second axis about which a rigid body homogeneous and of revolution can rotate. The system has two degrees of freedom. We have to study the motion of the system. There will be no force function. Only rotations are possible (two independent ones around AB and one around A'B').

Analytically, the two problems are one and the same, for in both cases, U = 0 and the coefficients E, F, 0 in 2 T are constants (which can always, by a linear transformation on x, y, be reduced

■•'

ANALYSIS SITUS

35

to E = G = 1, F = 0). Nevertheless, there is evidently no comparison between the motions in case (1) and case (2), so that to a certain extent, we are deceived by analytic methods. The assemblage of all possible positions of system (2) can be represented not on a plane, but on the surface of an anchor ring.

c

~D

Fig. 7.

We know since the researches of Poincar6 that the study of trajectories represented by differential equations must be founded on analysis situs. For instance, f(x, y, y') = 0 is geometrically represented by a certain surface, and on this surface defines a geometrical correspondence as follows: for each point of the surface it defines a certain direction (with its sense) in the tangent plane. We have then to draw at each point of the sur- face a curve which is tangent to the direction thus defined.

36 THIRD LECTURE

Poincare showed that such a problem cannot be handled unless we know what the genus of the surface is. This already appears in a simple preliminary question which arises in that study. We have said that we have a certain direction at each point of our surface. Can we in general do this without exception? In general we cannot. In each point, in general, we shall have a certain tangent direction defined, but there will be certain singular points in the correspondence. The only case in which the correspondence can be complete is when the surface is of genus one. For instance, there must be singular points for the genus zero. In that case, Poincare stated that every trajectory is either a closed one, or finishes in a singular point, or is asymp- totic to a closed curve. For genus one, singular points may be absent, but the shapes of curves verifying the equation may yet be much more complicated.

Differential equations of higher order will also of course (and did indeed in some parts of Poincare's work) require the inter- vention of analysis situs. But the difficulty will be much greater, as in hyper-spaces this theory becomes as complicated as it was simple in Riemann's hands when applied to ordinary surfaces. These higher chapters of analysis situs begin, however, to be well known, and though they could not hitherto be applied to differ- ential equations, their role is already clear, owing to the works of Picard and Poincare, in the natural generalization of Riemann's original theory. I mean the difficult theory of algebraic surfaces and algebraic functions of two or more independent variables.

In the line of partial differential equations, we must point out a very remarkable analogous example due to Volterra and con- cerning the problem of elasticity. Generally speaking, if the external forces and also the peripheric efforts acting on a homo- geneous solid body are zero, so will be the stress at every point of its substance. More precisely in such a body of simply con- nected shape, stress could only appear under those conditions if singular points would exist where they would cease to obey the general laws known for their distribution. But the contrary can

ANALYSIS SITUS 37

take place if the body has an annular form, and in fact Volterra practically constructed such annular bodies in which stress exists and can be experimentally perceived, without any external action and without any singular point.

3.

But examples of a much more elementary character, belonging to the very beginning of the differential calculus, can be given. Let us consider a point-to-point correspondence, defined by such equations as

X = /(*, y), Y = g(x, y).

When does that system of equations admit one and only one solution in x, y if X, Y are supposed to be given?

It is classical that this, above all, depends on the functional determinant

df df D(X,Y)

D(x, y)

dx dy

dg dji

dx dy

Suppose that this is not zero in a certain point x0, y0. We are taught that in the neighborhood of (X0, Y0) the system will have one and only one solution. The tempting conclusion is to suppose that if everywhere this determinant is not zero, then everywhere we will have a one-to-one correspondence. This is not true, and indeed errors have been committed on that subject. Even in the simplest case, in which the representation of the â– whole plane of XY on the whole plane of xy is considered, a sup- plementary condition at infinity must be added in order to ascertain that the transformation is one-to-one.

But now let us replace our planes by two spheres, a corre- spondence being considered between a point (x, y, z) of the surface of the first sphere, and a point (X, Y, Z) of the surface of the second. In this case we find that if a condition analogous to that above holds at every point of the first surface it will actually insure a regular one-to-one correspondence.

38 THIRD LECTURE

But if we replace our spheres by two anchor rings, the results will again be completely and utterly changed. Several points on the surface of one anchor ring may correspond to one and the same point on the surface of a second one, although in the neighborhood of each point everything seems to take place just as in a one-to-one correspondence. To see this, one has only to note that a point on the torus depends on two angles, 6, <p. If we call 0', <p' the two similar angles for the second surface, we have only to define the correspondence by 0' = pQ, <p' = q<p, p and q being two arbitrary integers.1

A curious fact is that the same thing occurs with respect to two circles. It is evident that if two points respectively move on the two circumferences with uniform speed, one turning exactly p times (p being an integer) while the other turns once, each position of the former will correspond to p distinct positions of the latter, although the ratio of speeds never changes signs, nor even becomes zero or infinite.

Nothing of the kind could, as we saw, occur on the surfaces of our two spheres (nor of two hyperspheres in r;-dimensional space, if n > 2), so that, in that respect, the case of two dimen- sions proves more complicated than that of three or more dimensional spaces.

These peculiar distinctions are closely connected with the fun- damental distinctions of analysis situs. They are due to the fact that there are many ways essentially distinct from each other, of

1 It is interesting to add that as far as ordinary (closed) surfaces are con- cerned, the genus 1 is the only one for which such a paradoxical circumstance can occur, in the sense that, if each point of a closed surface 2, of genus g > 1, corresponds to one (and only one) point of a second closed surface 2' of the same genus, and if, in the neighborhood of each point, the relation thus defined takes the character of a one-to-one regular correspondence, it is such on the whole surfaces.

This is easily seen in noting that, more generally, if we place ourselves under the same conditions except that we do not suppose the two genera, g, g' to be equal, and if h be the number of points of 2 corresponding to same point on 2 this number h (which must be the same everywhere, on account of the absence of singular points) is connected with g, g' by the equation g — 1 = h(g' — 1): a fact which results from the generalized Euler's theorem.

*,

ANALYSIS SITUS 39

passing from one point to another of a circumference (according to the number of revolutions performed around the curve) whilst any line joining two points of the surface of a sphere can be changed into any other one by continuous deformation.

This question of correspondences and Euler's theorem on polybedra would give us the most simple and elementary in- stances in which the results are profoundly modified by con- siderations of analysis situs, if another one did not exist which concerns the principles of geometry themselves. I mean the Klein-Clifford conception of space. But since this conception has been fully and definitively developed in Klein's Evanston Colloquium, there is no use insisting on it. We want only to remember that this question bears to a high degree the general character of those which were spoken of in the present lecture. Klein-Clifford's space and Euclid's ordinary space are not only approximately, but fully and rigorously identical as long as the figures dealt with do not exceed certain dimensions. Nothing therefore can distinguish them from each other in their infini- tesimal properties. Yet they prove quite different if sufficiently great distances are considered.

This example, as you see, exactly like the previous ones, teaches us that some fundamental features of mathematical solutions may remain hidden as long as we confine ourselves to the details; so that in order to discover them we must neces- sarily turn our attention towards the mode of synthesis of those details which introduce the point of view of analysis situs.

LECTURE IV

Elementary Solutions of Partial Differential Equations and Green's Functions

1. Elementary Solutions

The expressions we are going to speak of are a necessary base of the treatment of every linear partial differential equation, such as those which arise in physical problems. The simplest of them is the quantity employed in all theories of the classical equation of Laplace: V2m = 0; namely the elementary Newtonian potential 1/r, where

,2+^2=0

f- V(x-a)2+ (y - b)2 + (z - c)2

and (a, b, c) is a fixed point.

The potential was really introduced first and gave rise to the study of the equation. All known theories of this equation rest on this foundation. The analogous equation for the plane is

dx2+ dy2

Here we must consider the logarithmic potential, log 1/r, where r = V (x — a)2 -f- (y — b)2. By this we see that if we wish to treat any other equation of the aforesaid type, we must try to construct again a similar solution which possesses the same properties as 1/r possesses in the case of the equation of Laplace. How is such a solution to be found? To understand it, we must examine certain properties of 1/r. First let us note that that quantity 1/r is a function of the coordinates of two points (x, y, z) and (a, b, c) [the corresponding element log 1/r in the plane being similarly a function of (.r, y; a, b)]. If considered as a function of x, y, z, alone (a, b, c, being supposed to be con- stant) in the real domain, 1/r is singular for r = 0; and r = 0

40

1

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 41

only when x = a, y = b and z = c simultaneously. But for complex points, 1/r is singular when the line that joins (.r, y, z) and (a, b, c) is part of the isotropic cone of summit (a, b, c).

This isotropic cone is not introduced by chance, and not any surface could be such a surface of singularity. It is what we shall call the characteristic cone of the equation. We already met with the notion of characteristics in our first lecture, and saw that it is nothing else than the analytic translation of the physical expression "waves." I must nevertheless come back to it this time in order to remind you that the word "waves" has two different senses. The most obvious one is the following: Let a perturbation be produced anywhere, like sound; it is not immediately perceived at every other point. There are then points in space which the action has not reached in any given time. Therefore the wave, in that sense a surface, separates the medium into two portions (regions): the part which is at rest, and the other which is in motion due to the initial vibration. These two portions of space are contiguous. It was only in 1887 that Hugoniot, a French mathematician, who died prematurely, showed what the surface of the wave can be; and even his work was not well known until Duhem pointed out its importance in his work on mathematical physics.

A second way of considering the wave is more in use among physicists. We have not in the first definition implied vibrations. If we now suppose that we have to deal with sinusoidal vibra- tions of the classical form, the motion is general and embraces all the space occupied by the air. Tracing the locus of all points of space in which the phase of the vibration is the same, we determine a certain wave surface (or surfaces).

It is clear that these two senses of the word "waves" are utterly different. In the first case, we have space divided into two regions where different things take place, which is not so in the second case. Certainly, physically speaking, we feel a certain analogy between them. But for the analyst, there seems to be a gap between the two points of view.

42 FOURTH LECTURE

The gap is filled by a theorem of Delassus. Let us consider any linear partial differential equation of the second order, and sup- pose that u is a solution which would be singular along all points of a certain surface, irix, y, z) = 0. By making some very simple hypotheses as to the nature of the singularity, Delassus found that this surface must be a characteristic as defined in our first lecture; that is, it must verify, if the given equation is V2u = 0, the (non-linear) partial differential equation of the first order

{%)H%>&)'-°

obtained by substituting for the partial derivatives of the second order of the unknown function u in the given equation, the corresponding squares or products of derivatives of the first order of x (the other terms of the given equation being considered as cancelled). This is the characteristic equation corresponding to our problem. It is the same as the one found by Hugoniot in studying the problem from the first point of view. This third definition will show us the connection between the first two. In the first case, the wave corresponds to discontinuity, for the speeds and accelerations change suddenly at the wave surface: such a discontinuity is evidently a kind of singularity. In the vibratory motion the general equation contains the factor sin uir since u = F sin fiir, where F is the parameter corresponding to the frequency, and ir is a function of x, y, z. This form of u seems to show no singularity, for the sine is a holomorphic function It is nevertheless what one may call "practically singular." If we suppose that the absolute magnitude of n is large, the function varies very rapidly from + 1 to — 1, it has derivatives which contain u in factor, and these derivatives are therefore very large. It has a resemblance to discontinuous function because of the large slope. So that, in what may be called "approxima- tive" analysis, it must be considered as analogous to certain discontinuous functions. From that point of view the three notions of waves are closely connected.

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 43

This view of Delassus is the one which will interest us now because in the case of the elementary solution 1/r the char- acteristic cone is a surface of singularity. We see now in what direction we may look for the solution of the problem. We have to find what will be the characteristic cone or surface corresponding to it. Then we must construct a solution having this as a singularity. The first question is answered by the general theory of partial differential equations of the first order. We must have a conic point at (a, b, c). In general the char- acteristic cone is replaced by a characteristic conoid which has curvilinear generatrices which correspond to the physical "rays." Secondly, we must build a solution which will have this for a surface of singularity. The first work of general character in this direction was that of Picard in 1891. He considered the case of two variables and treated more especially the equation

d2u d2u (1) W+W=CU

Not every equation of the general type

. d2u , _ d2u , „ d2u , A„fc , „„3ti , „ AM+B3^+CW+2Dl>:r+2Eay+Fu=0

can be reduced to that form. But in the elliptic case (B2 —AC < 0) it can, by a proper change of independent variables, be reduced to the form

,,. d2u , d2u du du ,

(1) d?+W+adx+bdy+CU=°

(in which the characteristic lines are the isotropic lines of the plane). Sommerfeld and Hedrick treated this more general form and showed for equation (1), as Picard had done for the equation (1'), that there exists an elementary solution, possessing all the essential properties of log 1/r. It is

P log 1/r + Q

P and Q being regular functions of x and y. P has the value 1,

4

44 FOXTRTH LECTURE

x = a, y = b. In the hyperbolic case (real characteristics), the form to which the equation can be reduced is Laplace's form

, . d2u . du , , 3m ,

if the change of variables is real; and the corresponding ele- mentary solution is of the type

PlogV(*-o)(y-4) + Q

P and Q having the same significations as above (P is nothing else than the function which plays the chief role in Riemann's method for equation (2)). Of course, if imaginary changes were admitted (which is possible only if the coefficients are supposed to be analytic) elliptic equations, as well as hyperbolic ones, could be reduced to the type (2) or as well, (1). The only case in which that reduction is not at all possible, is when B2 — AC = 0, the parabolic case. This is a much more difficult case. It has been treated only recently. There is a new type of elementary solution which was given in 1911 by Hadamard in the Comptes Rendus, and for the equation of heat with more than two variables by Georey that same year (in the same periodical). Even if we leave the parabolic case aside, the question has a new difficulty arising because it is not possible to simplify by changing variables as before when there are more than two of them, so that we must then treat the general case. The problem was, however, first treated in the case of

du , , du , du , „ dx dy dz

But not every partial differential equation of the second order in three variables can be reduced to this form. It is important nevertheless. Holmgren obtained a solution in form analogous to 1/r, namely P\r, where P = 1 for r = 0.

If we wish to treat the general case where the coefficients are quite arbitrary, we must try first to form the surface of singu- larity which is the characteristic conoid. Suppose first that we

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 45

have any regular characteristic surface of our equation and suppose that by a change of variables, x = 0 is the surface. Let us write u = xpF (x, y, z). One can show that, giving p any positive value, solutions of this form can be found, F being regular. Such is not the case when p is a negative integer; and this gives us again an interesting illustration of the consider- ations explained in our first lecture in connection with Schoenflies' theorem. Let p be a negative integer and suppose that there is a solution. Then we have also other values of u of the form

F(x, y, z) i v , s — h Fi(x, y, z)

(We can form an infinity of these solutions because the differential equation possesses an infinity of regular solutions.) But those values of u can be written

F + x"Ft

So that, if our question is possible, it has an infinity of solutions. By the same reasoning as in the first lecture, we must not wonder at its being in general not possible. There is again this balancing between infinity of solutions and their existence.

But we have supposed our characteristic surface to be a regular one. If we deal with our characteristic conoid, which has (a, b, c) for a conic point, things behave differently; p cannot have an arbitrary value. If the number of independent vari- ables is n, we must have

n- 2 p= 5—, or

(-_ii+1), -(!=!+,).

The first of these values is, however, the only essential one, because, if we have formed the (unique) solution corresponding to p = — (n — 2)2, which depends on x, y, z, a, b, c, we can deduce all others from it : we need merely to differentiate with respect to a, b, c.

If n is even, those values of p become negative integers and

46 FOURTH LECTURE

therefore, on account of what we just said, there is, in general, no solution of the above form

We have to replace this by

« = ^ + p1iogr

in which T would again be equal to r2, r meaning a distance in n-dimensional space, if the higher terms (of the second order) of the given equation are of the form V2w- However, if these terms are arbitrary, T should be replaced by the first member of the equation of the characteristic conoid of summit (a, b, c).

The functions P, Q, Pi can easily be developed in convergent Taylor's series if the coefficients of the equation are analytic. If not, they still exist but are much more difficult to find. The first result of Picard, concerning the special equation (1'), was however, obtained (by successive approximations) without any assumption on the analyticity of c: Later, E. E. Levi solved the problem in the same sense for the general elliptic equation.

The principle of these methods of Picard and Levi in reality is the same. Both may be considered as peculiar cases of one indicated by Hilbert and consisting in the introduction of the first approximation, which presents a singularity of the required form, but does not need to verify the given equation. The investigation of the necessary complementary term leads again to an integral equation. I must add that, for equa- tions of a higher order, the extension of this seems to offer difficulties of an entirely new kind, owing to the fact that the characteristic conoid generally admits other singularities than its summit (viz. cuspidal lines). For the very special case in which there are no other terms than those of the highest order, the coefficients of those terms being constant, it has however been reduced to Abelian integrals by a beautiful analysis of Fredholm's.

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 47

2. Green's Functions Elementary solutions are a necessary instrument for the treatment of the partial differential equations of mathematical physics. They are not always sufficient. They are sufficient for the simplest of the problems alluded to in our first lecture, namely Cauchy's problem. But we know that for the ellip- tic case, this latter is not to be considered, and we have to face others, such as Dirichlet's problem. For Dirichlet's prob- lem (i. e. to find u taking given values all over the surface of the volume S, and satisfying y~u = 0), 1/r is not a sufficient function. We must introduce a new function of the form 1/r + h where h is a regular function; and h must be such that 1/r + h must be zero at every point of the boundary surface. This is called Greens Function. It is the potential produced on the surface S by a quantity of electricity placed at (a, b, c) interior to the surface, this surface being hollow, conducting, and main- tained at the potential zero. This is its physical interpretation.

For any other linear partial differential equation of the elliptic type, one has to consider such Green's functions in which the term 1/r is to be replaced by the elementary solution (so that, at any rate, the formation of this latter is presupposed), h still being a regular function (at least as long as (a, b, c) remains fixed and interipr to S).

Similar sorts of Green's functions are also known for higher differential equations, e. g. for the problem of an elastic plate rigidly fastened at its outline, the differential equation being then V2 V2u = 0 (in two variables x and y only) and the role of elementary solution being played by r2 log r.

Like 1/r and like the elementary solution itself, any Green's function depends on the coordinates of two points, A(x, y, z) and B(a, b, c). But the chief interest in the study of those Green's functions, the important difference between them and the above mentioned fundamental solutions, corresponds to a similar difference between Cauchy's and Dirichlet's problems, such as defined in our first lecture. To understand this, let us

48 FOURTH LECTURE

remember that each of those two problems depends on three kinds of elements:

1. A given differential equation;

2. A given surface (or hyper-surface in higher spaces) S;

3. A certain distribution of given quantities at the different points of S.

Each of those elements has of course its influence on the solution but not to the same degree. The influence of the form of the equation cannot but be a profound one. On the contrary, the influence of the quantities mentioned in 3 is comparatively superficial, in the sense that the calculations can be carried pretty far before introducing them. In other terms, if we compare this to a system of ordinary linear algebraic equations, the role of the first element may be compared to that of the coefficients of the unknowns (by the help of which such complicated expres- sions as the determinant and its minor determinants must be formed) while the role of the third element resembles that of the second members which have only to be multiplied respectively by the minor determinants before being substituted in the numerator.

But as to the role of our second element, the shape of our surface S, the answers are quite different according to cases.

If we deal with Cauchy's problem, that shape plays just as superficial a role as the third element. For instance, in Rie- mann's method for Cauchy's problem concerning equation (2), every element of the solution can be calculated without knowing the shape of S (which in that case is replaced by a curve, the problem being two-dimensional) till the moment when they have to be substituted in a certain curvilinear integral which is to be taken along S.

But matters are completely different in that respect in the case of Dirichlet's problem. While one can practically say that there is only one Cauchy's problem for each equation, there is, for the same and unique equation V2" = 0, one Dirichlet's problem for the sphere, one for the ellipsoid, one for the paral-

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 49

lelepipedon; and these different problems present very unequal difficulties.

It is clear that the same differences will appear in the mode of treatment corresponding to the two problems. The elemen- tary solution depends on nothing else than the given equation and the coordinates x, y, z, a, b, c, of the two points A, B.

The Green's function on the contrary depends, not only on this equation and these coordinates, but also on the form of the boundary S.1

The interesting question arising therefrom is to find how the properties of Green's functions are modified by the change of the shape of the surface. Let us replace S by S', defined by its normal distance 8n (which may be variable from one point of S to another). Take two given points A and B within S. Then there is a certain form of Green's function gBA for the surface S, and if we change from S to S', gA changes. The change is

«n * * f fd9nA d9nB* jo

danA

—j — is the rate of change of gA relative to the change of n.

Here 8ndS is an element of volume comprised between the surfaces S, S'. Similar formulas hold for Green's functio.ns for a plane area. They are like those given by the calculus of variations of integrals, though its methods are not directly applicable.

A curious consequence is that from all the Green functions for all the elliptic partial differential equations, we can deduce by proper differentiations expressions verifying one and the same integro-differential equation, namely

S0a = S<t>A<t>nZndS

The fact that in the second member of the equation (3), the coefficient of dndS is quadratic and symmetric with respect to

â– All these observations quite similarly hold for the "mixed problems" alluded to in our first lecture, and for the expressions introduced in their treatment corresponding to Green's functions.

50 FOURTH LECTURE

expressions depending on the points A and B respectively, is also an important one. Useful inequalities, which could not easily be obtained otherwise, can be deduced therefrom.

Besides that study of the variation of the numerical values of Green's functions, the influence of the shape of S can be studied from another point of view, I mean its influence on their analytical properties, and this has been the occasion for important recent results. The complementary term k in a Green's function remains regular as long as one of the points remains fixed and interior to the considered domain; but it offers a peculiar singularity when the two points A, B simultaneously approach the same point P of the boundary; and that singularity looks at first like a very difficult one. Its study is nevertheless simplified by the fact that it only depends on the shape of 5 in the immediate neighborhood of P.

Fig. 8. In the case of the plane, for instance, if two closed contours S, S', limiting two different areas have a certain arc MN in common1 (Fig. 8), if P is a point of this arc, and if G, G' be the two Green's functions corresponding respectively to those con- tours, the difference G — G' will be a completely regular function (admitting a development in a convergent Taylor's series) when A and B are both very near to P.

1 The two contours are understood to be one and the same side of that arc MN.

ELEMENTARY SOLUTIONS 51

We have now to inquire what the singularity of G, for instance, will be. After having received a first partial answer in interest- ing papers by several Italian geometers, this question has been completely solved by E. E. Levi for a function analogous to the ordinary Green's function, and more recently by P. Levy for this latter itself.

The answer thus obtained is remarkably simple in the case of two dimensions. P. Levy also works out the three-dimensional problem, but there the results are much more complicated.

As to Green's function as a whole (and not only the singular part of it) it must be well understood that its value for any two given points of the area or even such elements as its normal derivative in one point of the contour, profoundly depends on the form of every part of this latter, however distant from the point or points in question.

By paying attention to this fact, we must expect, on account of what was seen in the preceding lecture, that considerations of analysis situs will be important in that question. At first this does not seem to be the case, and the most important methods for the resolution of Dirichlet's problem are common to areas of any genus (although with some modifications of detail, as will be seen for Fredholm's method in Kellogg's Dissertation). But other views of the problem will show that the influence of analysis situs does exist here and is perhaps even more astonish- ingly profound than in any of the questions examined in our last lecture.

If we consider again Dirichlet's problem for an area in the plane, we shall see that the analytical properties of the corre- sponding Green's function are very different if that area has one or several boundaries.

Let us take the first case. In this case, the plane area can be represented conformally on a circle of unit radius with the origin as center. It is easily seen that, in such a conformal representation, Green's function keeps its values, and this brings to light a remarkable consequence concerning the six Green's

52 FOURTH LECTURE

functions generated by four points taken two by two. The six quantities have a relation between them and give rise to a peculiar sort of geometry, which not only resembles the ordinary non-Euclidean geometry, but can be reduced to it by a simple transformation.

In an area with two boundaries (annular area) matters are quite different. Schottky has shown that if we take two such areas, S, S', having each two boundaries, they are not in general conformally representable on one another. Each one of them will be represented on the area between two concentric circles. But the ratio of the radii of these circles must, in each case, be chosen properly, and, therefore, will not, in general, be the same for 2 and for 2'.

In this last case, the relation between the six Green functions will not hold, and the properties of our Green's functions will be far less simple. They will become still more complicated for more than two boundaries. We again have here an important instance of the role played by analysis situs in analytical prop- erties, and as we have stated that Green's functions are related to all the chief topics treated in our preceding lectures, this is perhaps the best conclusion to be given to the ensemble of them.

I

Hadamard, Jacques Salomon

Four lectures on mathematics

Physical & Applied Sci.

PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET

UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY